Fink on the Split Subject

Mark Linsenmayer

Partially Examined Life

2016-12-21

Fink on the Split Subject (Lacan vs. Sartre)

April 8, 2013 by Mark Linsenmayer

I ended our episode bemoaning that I feel like I still don’t understand this talk of “subject” as opposed to “self.” A few of you have made some good comments on this, but I’m still not satisfied. Let me pull a few things out of the Fink book:

  1. In chapter 2 about “The Nature of Unconscious Thought,” he concludes (on p. 22) by saying, “Now this way of conceptualizing the unconscious apparently leaves no room for a subject of any kind. There is a type of structure automatically and autonomously unfolding in/as the unconscious, and there as absolutely no need to postulate any kind of consciousness of this automatic movement.” This is all in line with Sartre (at least) and with Lacan’s view of the ego: while there is a self as object (the ego), as social creation that we have beliefs about (our “self-image”) and which exists in a social space, that self is NOT the subject, not the one that does our actions.

  2. Ch. 4 is called “The Lacanian Subject,” and Fink distinguishes (on p. 35) Lacan from the structuralists and post-structuralists:

“Structure seemed to excluce the very possibility of the existence of a subject… Lacan… maintains and defends both concepts–structure and subject–in a rigorous theoretical framework. Nevertheless, as he strips the subject of so many of the characteristics usually attributed to it in Western thought… it is not always easy to see what role is left to the subject…

Lacan says… “the subject is never more than supposed”… the subject is never more than an assumption on our part. [It’s] a necessary assumption for Lacan, a construct without which psychoanalytic experience cannot be accounted for…

  1. He then, throughout ch. 4, tells us what the subject is not: it’s not the Cartesian subject, it “is not the subject of the statement,” it “appears nowhere in what is said.” What it is is fleeting (p. 41): “this enunciating subject… only appears when a propitious occasion presents itself… [It] subsists only long enough to protest, to say ‘No.’ Once the subject has said his or her piece, what he or she has said usurps his or her place; the signifier replaces him or her; he or she vanishes… This subject has no other being than as a breach in discourse.” However, immediately after that (p. 42), Fink clarifies that this description “applies.. more specifically to what one might call the ‘Freudian subject’ than to the Lacanian subject.” You can see how this description of subject as breach sounds like the unconscious butting in, but per #1 above, the unconscious has no subject.

  2. Still in ch. 4 (p. 43), Fink describes the Lacanian subject as the inverse of the Cartesian subject. By Cartesian subject he’s referring to the “I think therefore I am” formulation, and taking this not as a deductive argument for a persistent subject (as Descartes did) but more in the way Hume and others took Descartes, which is to say that while thinking is going on, there is, at that moment, a subject, immanent in that experience. So the subject doesn’t exist over time, but is just a “point of view” while consciously thinking at a given moment. But according to Lacan, “the subject… cannot take refuge in an idyllic moment where thought and being coincide but is, rather, forced to choose one of the other. He can ‘have’ either thought or being, but never both at the same time.” Why? Well, because, again, per #3, Lacan is concerned with the unconscious: “Lacan thus seems to hold out for us some sort of prospect of a subject with true or real being that would be diametrically opposed to the false being of the ego, but this is not ultimately the case.” So Lacan is like Freud (#3), but yet not like Freud (per #1), and yet there is a subject in some sense (per #2), though it’s not a “substance” like Descartes’s subject, and presumably we can’t just say it’s the body itself either that is the subject, that “does” our actions.

  3. “The Split Subject” section (p. 45) says: “The subject is split between the ego… and unconscious…, between conscious and unconscious, between an ineluctably false sense of self and the automatic functioning of language… in the unconscious.

…The subject is nothing but this very split. …A speaking being’s two “parts” or avatars share no common ground… This momentous split is the product of the functioning of language… our alienation in language… While this split has nothing in common with the kind of agency we tend to associate with subjectivity, it is nevertheless already a first step beyond structure. Language as Other does not automatically make a subject of a homo sapiens child; it can misfire, as it does in psychosis… Though the subject is nothing here but a split between two forms of otherness–the ego as other and the unconscious as the Other’s discourse–the split itself stands in excess of the Other… The advent of the split subject signals a corresponding division or breakdown of the Other.

  1. “Beyond the Split Subject” (p. 46) elaborates the solution hinted at by the last couple sentences of #4. Lacan wants to retain allegiance to the Freudain quote sometimes translated as “where it was so I will be” (or “where the id was, so the ego will be”):

“I must become the place where “it” was or reigned… I here apperas as the subjct that analysis aims to bring forth: an I that assumes responsibility for the unconscious, that arises there in the unconscious linking up of thoughts which seems to take place all by itself, without the intervention of anything like a subject.

This I, or subject of the unconscious, as we might call it, is in general excluded at the level of unconscious thought. It comes into being, so to speak, only momentarily… But while it is just as… short-lived a subject as was that of the interruptions known as slips of the tongue… this specifically Lacanian subject is not so much an interruption as… the acceptance of responsibility for that which interrupts, a taking it upon oneself.

For Lacan claims that “one is always responsible for one’s position as subject.”

Again using Sartre for comparison: Sartre too emphasizes responsibility. You’re in bad faith if you don’t take responsibility for even your implicit (Sartre doesn’t like the word “unconscious;” the thinks that “unconscious thought” is self-contradictory) assessments of the world. We have ultimate control over our own attitudes, which include much of the way we interpret the world, whether we react positively or negatively to things that happen to us. Now, I have serious problems with this claim, but the point here is that Sartre can have such a view, and moreover believe in “subjectivity” in the sense that something like Descartes’s starting point has to the starting point for philosophy, without having anywhere in his theory a “subject.” Rather, again, there’s just the public ego (an object, not a subject), and NO transcendental subject lurking behind all of our experience (a la Kant), and consciousness itself, which is just nothing: just the form of the world itself in the phenomenological field.

Both Sartre’s and Lacan’s terminologies here are non-intuitive and non-conventional. If you want to say (as they both do) that identification of the public self with the agent of our actions is a mistake, then you have to tweak the language to accommodate your position. Sartre does this by turning to phenomenology and finds that while of course my body and my thoughts and all that feel like mine, that doesn’t mean that there was a “me” to have those things before the body and thoughts came along. Rather these phenomena, i.e. of the objects of our experience, are primary, and then “me” gets built off of that. I perceive, e.g. my emotions, and need to acknowledge those as me or be in bad faith. The self is built, but needs to be built coherently, and in consciousness of my freedom and responsibility in building it as it is.

Lacan likewise agrees that the self is built but for clinical reasons wants to separate the conscious ego, which is a product of the imagination (e.g. the mirror stage where we get an “image” of ourself) and the symbolic (languages as the Other’s desire) that’s a product of normal development but which involves a lot of self deception, from these identifications with the products of the unconscious which Lacan thinks are key in advancing therapeutically. While (per #1) there is no subject of the unconscious, I can take responsibility for the unconscious (well, bits of it) nonetheless: I can claim them, and call them “mine.” For Lacan, this describes the subject’s fleetingly coming into existence. The subject is essentially an action, not a substance, or more precisely, a phenomena encountered during an action. It’s important that the analysand use this “me” terminology so that he or he feels ownership; that’s just part of claiming responsibility.

To reiterate, I think this dispute is largely terminological: I don’t think either way of using or not using the term “subject” can be ideal, i.e. accord with our pre-philosophical notions of “I,” because these theories are meant to correct those pre-philosophical notions. Nonetheless, I find Lacan’s formulation unnecessarily obscure, and think he could just use “self” as an umbrella term for all the self-identifications here, whatever else he wants to say about their role in psychological health.

-Mark Linsenmayer

Noah says 

April 8, 2013 at 3:43 pm

“Sartre does this by turning to phenomenology and finds that while of course my body and my thoughts and all that feel like mine, that doesn’t mean that there was a “me” to have those things before the body and thoughts came along. Rather these phenomena, i.e. of the objects of our experience, are primary, and then “me” gets built off of that. I perceive, e.g. my emotions, and need to acknowledge those as me or be in bad faith. The self is built, but needs to be built coherently, and in consciousness of my freedom and responsibility in building it as it is.”

To me, this is the best theory of the “subject.” It reminds me of the times in which a though or feeling kind of “invades” my awareness. It feels like it belongs to someone else. I.e, I overhear somebody make a lame joke and I feel a sense of resentment to that person, but I realize that that feeling of resentment is completely irrational because (1) we all make lame jokes from time to time and there’s no reason to resent a person for it, and (2) resenting a whole person for one fucking joke is an incredibly superficial thing to do. When I feel like this, I usually try to take responsibility for it by explaining to myself that it is irrational and pointless; the resentment usually dissipates after this. I don’t know if this is what Sarte meant by constructing a “subject” or sense of “me” but I feel it at least brings you closer to self-understanding.

Also, I’m reminded of a Rick Roderick video where he speculates that some people don’t even know that they have a “self.” From the Sartrean point of view, I guess you could say that they don’t know they could build a “self.” I mean, can a person even really be said to have a “self-hood” if he spends all of his time working//watching sports//buying stuff//drinking with friends? There is no time for self-reflection. Any sense he might have of “needing to know himself” is easily pushed aside in favour of watching TV. I speak from experience here: I find I consume a lot more entertainment during those times where I feel alienation from myself and other people. 

I’m probably confused about this. Maybe Lacan and Sarte were too.

Wayne Schroeder says 

April 9, 2013 at 12:25 am

“Sartre’s . . . earliest studies, though phenomenological, underscored the freedom and by implication the responsibility of the practitioner of the phenomenological method. Thus his first major work, Transcendence of the Ego, in addition to constituting an argument against the transcendental ego (the epistemological subject that cannot be an object) central to German idealism and Hussserlian phenomenology, introduces an ethical dimension into what was traditionally an epistemological project by asserting that this appeal to a transcendental ego conceals a conscious flight from freedom. The phenomenological reduction that constitutes the objects of consciousness as pure meanings or significations devoid of the existential claims that render them liable to skeptical doubt-such a reduction or “bracketing of the being question” carries a moral significance as well [avoidance of responsibility].”

“The “authentic” subject, as Sartre will later explain in his Notebooks for an Ethics, will learn to live without an ego, whether transcendental or empirical, in the sense that the transcendental ego is superfluous and the empirical ego (of scientific psychology) is an object for consciousness when it reflects on itself in an objectifying act that he calls “accessory reflection.” His works take pains either to ascribe moral responsibility to agents individually or collectively or to set the ontological foundations for such ascriptions.” http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sartre/

While bailing on the transcendental ego of Kant, Sartre also bails on the ego, but leaves both the cognitive and empirical ego to fight it out in the midst of responsibility/freedom without either a ship or a rudder (C’est la vie, i.e., man up, i.e. I love this guy).

Subject: For Lacan, the problem with the Self is illusion (vs reality). What Lacan’s Subject allows is it’s foundation as retroactive: as 1)being, and then 2)being conscious. Upon 2) being conscious, the 1) being, both become connected retroactively (Lacan’s theory of time, not unlike Kant’s or even Derrida’s). Being preceeds consciousness, and only becomes confirmed by consciousness so that the present always refers to the past which has always already have been. Conceptualization always wants to be able to locate a Self/Subject/Person/Entity and therein leads to a cognitive illusion of coherence (Self, etc.) which misses the richness of being. 

The Real, for Lacan, is not synonymous with reality. Not only opposed to the Imaginary, the Real is also exterior to the Symbolic. Unlike the latter, which is constituted in terms of oppositions (i.e. presence/absence), “there is no absence in the Real.” Whereas the Symbolic opposition “presence/absence” implies the possibility that something may be missing from the Symbolic, “the Real is always in its place.” If the Symbolic is a set of differentiated elements (signifiers)–(we live mostly in the world of the symbolic with occasional lightning bolts in the night’s sky), the Real in itself is undifferentiated—it bears no fissure. (As in Deleuze’s Virtual)

The Symbolic introduces “a cut in the real” in the process of signification: “it is the world of words that creates the world of things—things originally confused in the “here and now” of the all in the process of coming into being.” The unconscious is structured like a language. The Real is that which is outside language and that resists symbolization absolutely. 

In Seminar XI Lacan defines the Real as “the impossible” because it is impossible to imagine, impossible to integrate into the Symbolic, and impossible to attain. It is this resistance to symbolization that lends the Real its traumatic quality. Finally, the Real is the object of anxiety, insofar as it lacks any possible mediation and is “the essential object which is not an object any longer, but this something faced with which all words cease and all categories fail, the object of anxiety par excellence.”

Mark, I thus firmly disagree that “this dispute is largely terminological” but is in fact ontological. Lacan understood something essential that Sartre missed.


teleogram says 

April 9, 2013 at 7:56 am

Isn’t there a funny paradox in Lacan using “the Real” to signify this non-verbal area of experience, with those portentous capital letters to make us really sit up and pay attention to the symbol that he’s using? If he’d called it “this interesting concept I’ve got about un-symbolized senses and urges and feelings and stuff, so whaddya think, guys?” instead of “the Real” it would completely change the way people reacted to the concept, for instance. As such “the Real” seems to me to be a particularly poor choice for symbolizing what is supposed to be unsymbolizable, because it’s so loaded and heavy and symbolic already.

	Wayne Schroeder says 
	April 9, 2013 at 8:58 am
	Right on–Deleuze calls the Real the Virtual (with a capital)
	

dmf says 
April 9, 2013 at 10:09 am
http://kuscholarworks.ku.edu/dspace/bitstream/1808/9061/1/Auslegung.v10.n01%2602.057-064.pdf

	Wayne Schroeder says 
	April 9, 2013 at 11:09 am
	
	dmf–  Gardner’s conclusion: “And so the choice as I see it lies between accepting an intact and undivided cogito haunting a divided person, as we have in effect in Lacan; and rediscovering Sartre to find all of the splits of selfhood contained within a complexified and split cogito. I hope to have justified a preference for the latter, and thereby for according an oblique and qualified primacy to intentionality over signification.” 
	
	Gardner is not dealing with the difference between self and subject reflected in the PEL discussion and thus he conflates self and subject as cogito, resulting in a superficial reading of Lacan. He doesn’t do much better with Sartre, and seems to have a Cogito nostalgia without clear definitions of “self.”
	

Carter says 

June 10, 2014 at 4:19 pm

I wonder if the difference between public ego (Sartre) and subversive symptom (Lacan) can be relegated to Lacan’s understanding of sexual difference. If both masculinity and femininity are part of the human experience, perhaps these are the two types of subjectivity: public being (masculinity) and realist thought (femininity).

	
	Wayne Schroeder says 
	
	June 11, 2014 at 11:57 am
	
	Interesting, but it does not fit Lacan’s categories, the three registers, within which he defines sexuation in much more complexity than masculine vs feminine. In fact, masculine and feminine for Lacan do not even equate to male versus female.
	

JanneM says 

March 23, 2015 at 10:55 am

At the moment I believe that the subject refers to the spesific event that takes place at the analytic’s room when the process has it’s succesfull moment: when the connection or link is made, that which is pursued as the main target of the psychoanalytic therapy.

This moment is portraited on the cover of the Fink’s book, by the lightning that connects sky and earth – unconscious and conscious (ego).

I have no idea how to put it in words, but I believe I know it by experience. And it’s not limited to analytic setting (but is probably most notable there, since it will grasp the attention of both parties in question).

Trackbacks Douglas Hofstadter’s “I Am a Strange Loop” on the Self | The Partially Examined Life Philosophy Podcast | A Philosophy Podcast and Blog says: April 9, 2013 at 3:26 pm […] our Lacan episode and my comparison of Lacan with Sartre, you might think that this “no self” deal was just a Continental idea. If you remember […]


Previous Entry Next Entry

« Allegorical Knowledge Mass Authentic »